William James Lectures
5-6
Lecture 5-Pragmatism
and Common sense
In learning from the last lecture
that pragmatism tends towards plural direction we can again agree it certainly
is at least by simple additive function; things being joined if only by the
concept ‘and’. This is tough for the monists as they must then assume gain/loss
to the eternal. Now, turning towards the concept of knowledge, James argues
that it begins in locations of varying degree and can grow and spread. With
pragmatism, knowledge grows gradually and often in the restricting of opinions.
If a person were to break routine, stand up and yell it would cause you to pragmatically
restructure your opinion of them. In this the mind becomes strained between old
belief and the new fruits of experience. Thus, minds grow in areas and spread; however,
ideally as little as possible as not to alter old knowledge too much. So, we
fight the spread of mind’s new knowledge upon us, patch it up after and move
forward with the newly settled knowledge. Now in addressing the main topic at
hand of common sense, James wants to consider it as a continuum connecting us
to ancient ancestors concerning crucial methods of thinking preserved throughout
history. Common sense can be viewed in several ways, practically wise it is a person’s
good judgement. Philosophically wise it is a bit more technical as being, a
type of intellectual thought. Concerning common sense, an age-old method, particularly
by rationalists, has always concerned conceptuals like, thing, same/different,
minds, bodies, one time, one space. Context like this made it difficult to see
the ancestors working to separate realities from experiences as they did not
see a need too. But newer truths give us words like ‘thoughts’ thus
neutralizing thoughts as realities and instead reclassifying them. Surely it
feels like common sense for us to view time as a single straight line but with
regards to science we know that time is inconsistent. But, practically speaking
we know this inconsistency is not a good representation of human experience and
also such cosmic maps would be read with imaginary conceptuals and numbers
themselves. But certainly, we saw the benefits from the imaginary conceptuals
like ‘kinds’ or ‘sameness’ has with the conception of ‘the many’ we certainly
would not want to discard such powerful concepts either, pragmatically we must
hover in the in between. In everyday life common sense persists and is hard to
deny even if just simply the concept of self or body. Rationalists enjoy common
sense but use it far too technical in man’s relation to the divine; pragmatically
speaking, it is in a person’s intellect the words meaning and its influential
function. Science and philosophy also press the boundaries of common sense; concerning
scientific realism, objects secondary qualities seem to become unreal and concerning
critical philosophy, there is no common sense in being, its just a trick of the
mind. However, again we see that critical thought in science has given us
practical tools, clocks, medicine, telephones, all coming from the results of external
circumstances. This is our newer practical control over nature which common
sense certainly utilizes. Science is expanding too rapidly for the average public
common sense to keep up. Critical philosophy is useful, but it has little
pragmatic value. Thus, we have three highly comparable forms of thought of the
world, common sense, scientific, and critical philosophy. If common sense were
the most true then why would science also regard their qualities as secondaries
while it also itself even uses the imaginary world of lines and curves? All
three conceptions of truth are better for spheres of life. In concluding this,
common sense as truth assumes the copying by the mind of a given reality. And
by this James will argue, the conflict of truth between these three is why we should
reevaluate our notion of truth.
Lecture 6-Pragmatism’s
Conception of Truth
To start, James wants to address
truth as meaning: agreement with reality, since a true idea must copy its
reality. Our mental conceptions of the physical do copy; take a clock on the
wall, visualize it and you have a mental copy. But, concerning its internal
mechanics, it is not too accurate. So, if it is not exact but we trusted our conception
beforehand, what does that say about our agreements with objects? To idealists?
Well, what is true is realized by divine revelation thus, mental frameworks
like mental copying appear as being from the divine. To pragmatists? If it is true,
it is verifiable, if it is false, it is not, this is the practical difference
in ideas. Truth would not be inherent; it happens to an idea being made true by
events and then verified. Verification and validation are practical at
signifying the practical consequences, a great example being the agreement
formula which concerns whether our ideas and their consequences agree with
reality. Agreements insinuate realities that help conduct our actions and ideas,
this is the function of ‘agreeable leading’ or the idea’s verification.
Concerning pragmatism, thoughts that are true thoughts are valuable by actions,
true not as ends but as means to more crucial ends. An example such as seeing
animals may signify the true fact that something was there, but the tracks may
be more crucial for signaling food in times of starvation. A pragmatic value of
truth comes at the right times as needed, thus also the importance of latent truths.
When a stored truth ever becomes practical it resurfaces, its need satisfies
the verification, passes over it, and we call it a truth. Our thoughts and
beliefs commonly pass over as well as long as not challenged as that would push
for a direct verification and thus reassessment. Generally, people assume things
exist as kinds, we see one causation and assume it over. People then become
conditioned to the life behavior that repeats for us correctly a good 99% of
the time but without ever truly verifying, as the results do not press for it. Thus,
partial verification is confirmed in a commonsense regard as verification does
not only concern the external but also the internal of mental ideas. Examples
like 2+2=4 or that gray is between black and white; these feel of common sense,
and we do not seek an external verification. Now, in concerning truth as
guiding, or leading, we hold our eternal or deep personal truths to heart and
we use the external reality to write facts best fit, the marriage of fact and
theory. This ‘leading’ is the essential nature as it determines its ‘fit-ness’
in the world. The persuasiveness of leading commonly passes as an indirect
verification for the experience but when one concerns it as true it always
comes back to external verification. This is a rough pragmatic take on
agreement. James now points towards truth-processes such as health or wealth.
Truth is made just as health is experienced; health is lived in things like
digestion or sleep. We commonly pass over the verification as we trust the
ideas of the past has worked well for much of common sense. Thus, we can see we
have a massive amount of indirectly verified ideas that work better as such, say
I have not been but someone else told me that Japan was a real place. Looking
at Aristotle, we see his distinction between habit and act; health in action is
seen as good sleep or digestion but, a healthy person cannot always do these
but rather only when necessary. Thus, they become habits, truth as well also
becomes a habit of belief and ideas. Concerning the absolute truth, nothing can
alter it; this is hard as most past truths were discarded when new ones arose thus,
they were only relative truths. When new truths are found they feel as if they
have always existed as true. Now, with the future mass influx of verification that’s
inevitable experience’s partial truth’s must address an almost absolute truth
as to address the totality of their beliefs. People invest in beliefs as a
means of value and when applied to life it becomes action in reality,
readjusting our beliefs. Concerning the rationalist’s absolute, truth has
nothing to do with the practical and our agreements are only relative. But the pragmatic
would argue that just like truth-processes like health or wealth that truth is conditionally
relative. Truth is as necessary as un-true even if just in verification but,
un-truths are not real things thus it would be a relative truth and not an
absolute. It is general conditions and consequences that limit our abstract
imperatives thus truth is relative and must be treated pragmatically or, in
agreement with the reality that we see truth lies in the concrete and
experiential.
My thoughts: Common sense has a
strong pragmatic value and creating the conceptual helps to separate and not
confuse common sense and critical understanding in daily life. I would enjoy talking
through some different common sense utilitarian possibilities, one that I think
about; does it give us more pragmatic value to hold a commonsense regard for
the afterlife? The being, we just do not know. Even empirically we do not know
what happens truly after death, thus the conversation becomes idle and needs
practical settlement. And suddenly the commonsense reality of ‘I don’t know’ to
an afterlife feels to hold more real-world cash-value. Also, truth as agreement
is really compelling for pragmatic purpose. However, I did have some
difficulties understanding his rationalist’s arguments against agreement.
--Seth Graves-Huffman
Just a personal note: I have started re-reading Richardson’s biography, and I was struck by this sentence in the Prologue: “James’s best [work] is urgent, direct, personal, and useful.” That, of course, is what I love about James, and what is reflected in my essays about his essays. I always see exhortations regarding how to live.
ReplyDeleteThese lectures, V & VI, along with the others in Pragmatism, exemplify why I regard James as such a good teacher. He introduced me here to denkmittel, thought instruments. He makes a connection between thought and language. A real Wittgensteinian. He helps me think rationally about the growth of knowledge. He provides insight into the foundations of truth, and overhauls the very idea of truth. He provides a conception of truth that is useful to me, i.e., pragmatic. Our theories about knowledge are denkmittel; i.e., instrumental, mental modes of adaptation to reality.
Same here. I love this passage from Lec.VI:
Delete"The 'absolutely' true, meaning what no farther experience will ever alter, is that ideal vanishing-point towards which we imagine that all our temporary truths will some day converge. It runs on all fours with the perfectly wise man, and with the absolutely complete experience; and, if these ideals are ever realized, they will all be realized together. Meanwhile we have to live to-day by what truth we can get to-day, and be ready to-morrow to call it falsehood..."
"If a person were to break routine, stand up and yell it would cause you to pragmatically restructure your opinion of them. In this the mind becomes strained between old belief and the new fruits of experience." Indeed. When people violate norms and expectations, especially in outrageous ways, we typically think it prudent to revisit and revise our previous stock of presumptive truths about them in the light of this surprising new evidence. These days, though, many of our contemporaries seem dogmatically wedded to their positive preconceptions about some people no matter how outrageously they behave. (Maybe you can guess who I'm thinking of, in particular...)
ReplyDelete"Rationalists enjoy common sense but..." A big but for WJ. Recall what he said in Lec. I about Leibniz and "rationalist minds" etc.
"Critical philosophy is useful, but it has little pragmatic value." Maybe for the general public, in an un-philosophic age. But WJ definitely thinks critical reflection has great pragmatic value for the philosophically inclined.
"All three conceptions of truth are better for spheres of life." Yes, so long as we don't conflate or confuse our spheres: "Common sense is BETTER for one sphere of life, science for another, philosophic criticism for a third; but whether either be TRUER absolutely, Heaven only knows."
"...does it give us more pragmatic value to hold a commonsense regard for the afterlife?" Here is a good example of what WJ would mean by calling truth "relative" (though I think the better word might be "relational"): for some, there IS greater value for life in the notion of a supernatural afterlife, for others there is not. Some of us are more motivated by concern for the natural afterlife of those who will survive us on earth. But WJ will not generalize about this. What is better for life is always dependent on the liver, his/her entire biography and core values, how he/she relates to others and to life at large, etc. etc.
"...his rationalist’s arguments against agreement" -- WJ admits the formal correctness of "agreement with reality," he just thinks the concept is vacuous and unhelpful in a practical sense. We have no way of standing detached from both the world and our statements about the world in order to observe a "correspondence," so we have to interpret that notion in some other way. He proposes interpreting it in terms of how well beliefs and actions "lead" us in navigating our whole experience, rather than seeking verification of a precise correspondence between words and world -- an impossible undertaking, as even Wittgenstein eventually conceded -- at every step.
Rationalists like his friend Royce, recognizing the practical vacuity of corresondence, often opted for a coherence theory of truth: a belief is true when it can be construed as cohering best with the rest of our beliefs... so there's nothing external to the complete set of them to which it/they must be shown to "correspond." But of course there are problems with that approach to, and WJ really (I think) has little patience for any merely-theoretical attempt to articulate the meaning of truth. We need to evaluate truth as we evaluate health in terms of what is better for us... "in the long run and on the whole of course":
"'The true,' to put it very briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as 'the right' is only the expedient in the way of our behaving. Expedient in almost any fashion; and expedient in the long run and on the whole of course; for what meets expediently all the experience in sight won't necessarily meet all farther experiences equally satisfactorily. Experience, as we know, has ways of BOILING OVER, and making us correct our present formulas."