The Varieties of
Religious Experience Lectures 3, and 4 & 5 (Part 1)
Lecture 3- The
Reality of the Unseen
The human relation with objects
adopts many attitudes including moral, practical, or even religious. We are
most commonly aware of these relations by our senses but also by our mere
thoughts and oddly, many times these thoughts may have a stronger effect on us
and our attitudes than the former objective sensations. If someone insulted me,
I may be more upset about it the next day in memory then when I was in the
moment that it occurred in. For most western religions, especially Christianity,
visions are rather rare thus most followers, institutional ones, generally base
religious ideas within the practical present. Certainly, religion has concrete
objects but it feels more full of abstract objects; God's attributes such as
justice, holiness, mercy, etc. (p54). All of which greatly influence pragmatic
practicalities such as meditation. In a reassessment to abstract objects James
offers a Kantian approach, objects of belief in God, such as design, soul,
freedom, are not exactly objects of knowledge at all (p54-55) as they do not
concern sense, thus there is no significance in discussing. But, James defends,
there is certainly meaning in our practices; we can act as if there were a God,
feel as if one were free, consider plans for immortality (p55), as these words
make a significant practical difference in lives. With Kant, just an idea of
what these objects ‘might be’ gives positive reason to conceive it. For James,
Kant is another outer limit of religions exaggerations, or sentiments of
reality; these sentiments attach to personal objects of belief that can be a
lasting mark for the rest of one's life. Abstractions enliven human’s realities
and actions and as such we treat them as objects and permit worldly space and
realities for them. As we saw prior, this can also be a less religious and more
moralist, Emersonian, take, with a universe of concrete objects swimming in the
higher universe of abstract ideas. Now James offers a particular take of an
author on Greek gods as being only “half-metaphoric personifications” (p58) of
abstract laws that separate nature, ie., feeling the smile of the sun, the bite
of winter, and so on - with these Greeks offers us at least reference to a human
sphere of subjectivity. With this, the Greek pantheon at least argues human
beings a sense of feeling, one deeper and more special than most experienced
from our normal sensations. If we take this as so, maybe we can awaken this by
exciting our normal senses, thus by Kant, if something else equally excites our
senses it would appear real. And, if religious concepts do touch this deep subjective,
they will certainly be believed in in spite of criticism, and this is
interestingly true with visions and hallucinations. Generally, these are
relative and imperfect events and often particular realities and sensations
occur of which can be as unique as the feeling of a presence not there. The
majority of this lecture James gives personal testimonials, religious and not,
that are relative to the discussion. These realities almost give chills on
their events and the genuinity of the individuals. Starting with a non-religious
individual, an academic actually, in a hotel out of town they feel an odd
presence about, turning into a difficult psychological situation. Later they
meet similar means but with a complete bliss of joy with a will to believe such
a beautiful reality that they experienced is more real than anything else they
have ever known. Not religious, but it certainly could be. He then gives
several more examples of people experiencing ‘odd presences’ that some
interpret is God, some spiritual; another example of a blind person, without
any ability to distinguish lights or colors, sees a vision of a bearded man in
a suit slipped under his door (p62). As if an abstract conception exuded
feelings of space and reality, an idea living within reality. Thus at least
arguing a human reality with mental function to sense presence, a sense deeper
than our usual ones. James continues examples, not only positive conceptions of
presence but also negative; an individual reflects on life and they are more
ready to take it as it is not and this reality must be a dream, James argues
this finds a correlation with suicide, but that is for later discussion. Now it
is becoming clear that with a religious temperament people may “possess objects
of belief as a quasi-reality directly apprehended” (p64) and often one sense of
presences’ apprehended fluctuates so thus too does one's use(s) positively and
negatively. One example of a negative use was from a person reminiscing of a
past in which they related with the universe as an ‘It’ and without ‘It’ now
they feel void and know what is not there. Another example, with the person
feeling all around them the limits of what they cannot feel thus feeling the
two realities meet, feeling unity with a negative presence. They said to be
more willing to doubt themselves than with the presence felt. All examples thus
far have certainly shown how vast the range of the human ontological
imagination is, unpicturable beings with an intensity near hallucination and at
many times with personified relations, commonly as lovers in a cosmic relation.
And experiences for people generally bring an overwhelming convincingness thus
it is fair to say that of all the examples thus far, as fallible as they may be,
are at least genuine perception of truth attempting to be shared. The most
common way to oppose such mysticism in philosophy is by using rationalism, as
rationalism emphasizes ‘beliefs ought to be able to be articulated’. Thus,
James argues four necessities for the grounds of rationalism: one, definite
stable abstract principles, two, definite facts of sensations, three, definite hypothesis
based on such facts, and four, definite inferences logically drawn (p73). Things
that are too vague to define do not belong in a rational system, with
philosophy and science being a resultant of rational realities. But, surely at
some extent we see the superficiality relative within it, the part constantly
challenging for proofs and logic chopping (p73). Rationalism in general has a
hard time converting another's perspective if the individual’s ‘intuitions’ are
opposed to rationalism's points. Certainly one's consciousness is its totality
including subconscious, desires, impulses, etc., thus compromising much of a
beings ‘innate’ reality and the attitudes reacting to conflicting rationalism.
This rational inferiority is clear when arguing for or against religion,
referring back to Kant, it should not be rationally argued. Within metaphysics
and religion both articulate reasons but these rationalisms have come only once
our unarticulated feelings have made their impression upon us with a general
point made (p74). Then intuition can work with reason, growing together. Thus,
how religious systems grow, age, and change with time. James's aim here was in
no way to claim the subconscious as superior rather, he is just laying out
realities. However, certainly with what we have seen “so much for our sense of
reality with religious objects” (p75). Now, as we saw, many factors necessitate
their opposites, as to not take a life too serious one must be able to
understand it first as serious. Thus, the evenly tempered solemn religious
follower takes their peace carefully as they still walk with danger in mind and
the fact that not all can be held in check, “lie low rather, lie low; for you
were in the hands of a living God” (p76). Next, we get a great example with an author’s
take on the Book of Job; for them, the real problem with people’s general
conclusions is that people take it too serious rather than reflecting
solemnities attachment of ‘to not take life too serious’ to then be able to
analyze what is apparent to them. That, life is a burden for man and that man
is not a pure reflection of creation but rather sees it where he applies himself.
It is that man must apply choice as “it is transcendent everywhere” (p76). It
is even tempting to call such authors takes as religious, as Professor Seeley argues,
“any habitual or regulated admiration is worthy of being called religion” (p77),
even such as music, math, and ‘civilizations’, as much as they are admired and
believed in.
Lectures 4 and 5- The
Religion of Healthy-Mindedness (Part 1 p78-90)
To ask someone ‘what is the primary concern in life?’ We commonly hear answers concerning happiness. Truly the value of happiness polarizes around the lives and morals of humans daily. And it is certainly fair to say if happiness produces such admiration it can nearly be warranted a religion. Regardless, we should keep looking into religion specifically as if the two can be somewhat synonymous and if so then the more complexity in religion the greater the possible depths to human happiness. Often people seek the more complex when the gift of life slows its satisfaction. Concerning life's chief value of happiness, with religion generally happiness will satisfy the individual enough to work as proof, typically within immediate inferences and experiences. James shares an individual’s testimony concerning their close presence with God and the feelings of happiness they experienced were near impossible to articulate their overwhelming value. With this they believe such relations and feelings to be the “most indispensable proof of God's reality” (p79). To them nothing else is nearly as convincing. Now James aims to go to more simple religious examples. For many happiness is immediately particular thus it is rather transient such as causing emotions which may later evolve into forms of “enthusiasm and freedom” (p79). We are not only concerning a hedonistic reality of happiness but also of those that positively refuse any unhappiness ever present to the individual. Within the complete depths of human history there's always been groups of people with the aim of avoiding anything bad in life by accepting all that is natural. James gives a great example of Saint Augustine, “if you but love (God), you may do so as you incline” (p80), with James arguing this as one of the most morally profound observations to those that can grasp its meaning (p80). It is an example of a definite religious attitude, with evil to be overcome it exudes optimism. James then introduces Newman’s ‘once-borns’ and ‘twice-borns’ with once-borns put into a world of happiness and a contentment with it as they “no more shrink from God, then a child from an emperor, before whom the parents tremble” (p81). To them, God's character is harmonious with nature and present in its kindness and beauty. They certainly have very little concern with sin affecting them. And oddly this certainly relates with ancients of whom in “classics you find no consciousness of sin” (p81). They we were certainly conscious of vices but not as being an offence to God rather than themselves. Also, ancients did not often complain about evil rather than accept it, but some people do not learn evil to exist at all. With an example of a Unitarian preacher, we have someone arguing the importance of raising children in a simple and rational religious household, and that nothing could be better. If so, they may never know religious struggles and when met with future endeavors they are ready to use God's infinite strength in any difficulty. Thus, the child has a much greater chance at making it than twice-born, where the world is wrath and good is impossible (p83). Certainly, first-born’s feel to exude an almost pathological happiness compared to twice-borns great embrace of despair. Next, we get a testimonial of a disciple of Walt Whitman and the kind of person he actually was. Whitman had such an intense appreciation for anything natural and oddly, seemed to appreciate and love all people the same. They never heard Whitman complain about anything or anyone, almost as if he did not possess the ability to. It was also hard to tell if he truly feared. Walt Whitman’s literature success certainly has some relation to his cool temperaments, and he works through us, the reader, as a meliorist. While not directly religious Walt Whitman held strong life convictions and certainly understood and recognized sin but possessed such confident composure to write in spite of sin. Whitman refuses to adopt any conception of a sad mortality, and as we speak of removing unhappiness from happiness we can turn back again to the ancients, Greeks and Romans, in their consistency in keeping happiness and sorrow directly separate. For many ancients good was good and bad was bad and they did not deny the despairs of nature with no aim to escape from this world to a better one, possibly through imagination. To Walt Whitman, however, good was perfect and bad was perfect, Whitman disposes the reader to optimism and by that regard James respects him within a “genuine lineage of the prophets” (p87). Now it is looking possible to narrow a definition for ‘healthy-mindedness’: “the tendency which looks on all things and sees that they are good” (p87), with an ability to differentiate between voluntary and non-voluntary healthy-mindedness. Involuntary would be immediate happiness, voluntary or systemic as using an abstraction of conceiving a ‘good’. In this, one must pick several attributes as the essences for the short time being thus disregarding all other aspects. So, a volunteer systemic healthy-mindedness puts good as the primary importance and meaning to life and deliberately excludes evil from any perspective. Now, with happiness being an emotional state it certainly has criticisms and blindness especially concerning conflicting facts. Within happiness evil cannot exist, as to be actively happy they do not have time for it. Thus, explaining the odd behaviors of some as they put in maximum effort to ignore evil. This act of their continued silencing is near religious in nature. Concerning evil, it has a lot to do with an inner temperament, such as a fight or flight. But, to turn away from evil, the facts may remain, but the evil character no longer exists (p89). Now, in adopting optimism and turning back to philosophy, unhappiness begins to have an ugly nature. Attempting to restrict it may cause more problems and considering it bad only causes more evil to exist in situations thus, obviously we ought to reduce this. However, James argues when looking at ‘the bad’ philosophically speaking, it is easy to see the sublime of the reverse side of ‘good’. But this only brings evil back into sight thus to combat this one needs a true systemic conception of optimism for such moments that arise, similar to Walt Whitman with a frame entirely of good. With examples like a patriot, a lover, or a devote, all certainly have significant different conceptions of what evil is or is not thus, too many a sense of victory in the gravestone. In these states goods and bads are consumed within a “higher denomination, an omnipotent which engulfs the evil and which the human being welcomes as the crowning experience of his life” (p90). In the beginning we saw a primary concern in human lives is happiness and we can now see that a systemic healthy-mindedness religious attitude certainly lines up with those life concerns. As we commonly know we do not pay attention to disease death etc., as much as we can generally help it. With that we see the world of poetry or literature looks much more desirable than that of the real world.
--Seth Graves-Huffman
FYI- Questions from last Spring's MALA Experience course pertaining to VRE III: https://rationalitymt.blogspot.com/2023/01/questions-feb-7.html
ReplyDelete...and to VRE IV, V: https://rationalitymt.blogspot.com/2023/02/questions-feb-14.html
"we can act as if..." [god, freedom, immortality etc.]-- and for WJ, we SHOULD act as if these objects of belief are real IF doing so has practical value for living AND if something in our experience seems to compel that action. Acting "as if" is NOT, contra (eg) Bertrand Russell, pure make-believe.
ReplyDelete“any habitual or regulated admiration is worthy of being called religion”-I wonder what kind of "regulation" is required, by this definition?
"Abstractions enliven..."-- And when they do, they become more concrete through the actions they inspire. When they fail to inspire, they become intellectualist dogmas and fetishes.
"higher universe of abstract ideas"-- Plato and Emerson are at home with this notion, I don't think WJ quite is. When abstract ideas "enliven" etc., they cease to be mere abstractions and they DO enter into the familiar universe of our everyday experience.
"These realities almost give chills..."-- I think we'd better put quotes around 'realities'... And they don't give chills to those of us not predisposed to entertain supernatural speculation about their provenance. Some people say the book/film "The Exorcist" gave them chills. Just gave me a chuckle.
"with a religious temperament people may “possess objects of belief as a quasi-reality directly apprehended”..."-- And this is where I'm challenged, as a secular naturalist, to stay entirely sympathetic with WJ's project ("my religious act") of "defending experience against philosophy" when a little more philosophy might encourage a healthier skepticism regarding "quasi-realities directly apprehended"...
"religion...should not be rationally argued"-- But most religious people want NOT to be labeled as irrationalists (Kierkegaardians excepted, apparently) and must to that extent be open to rational challenges to specific religious claims and perhaps as well to the overall rationality of faith. They can't have it both ways, immunity to critique AND to the charge of unreason.
In my Ph'y of Happiness course currently we're about to read and discuss a new book called "Against Happiness"... (there's also an older book of the same title that I used years ago). Wonder what WJ would say.
ReplyDeletehttps://books.google.com/books?id=VfiZEAAAQBAJ&newbks=1&newbks_redir=0&lpg=PP1&dq=against%20happiness&pg=PP1#v=onepage&q=against%20happiness&f=false
https://books.google.com/books?id=KREKDJVDuo4C&newbks=1&newbks_redir=0&lpg=PP1&dq=against%20happiness&pg=PP1#v=onepage&q=against%20happiness&f=false
"To Walt Whitman, however, good was perfect and bad was perfect, Whitman disposes the reader to optimism and by that regard James respects him"... Well, WJ is ambivalent about WW. Someone who is really incapable of distinguishing good from bad is not going to be much of a meliorist, since the point of that view is to make bad things better.
ReplyDeleteAs I understand him, WJ says it's the once-born, the sky-blue optimist, who "deliberately excludes evil from any perspective"... the voluntarily healthy-minded have to work at acquiring a positive disposition despite their unshakable acknowledgement of the reality of evil.
"happiness being an emotional state"-- but for WJ it's equally a volitional state, or as we've come to say: happiness is a choice.
"Within happiness evil cannot exist"--but it must. WJ could not "blink the evil out of sight," yet he was committed to the pursuit of happiness.
"one needs a true systemic conception of optimism"--but meliorism is enough for a pragmatist. "It is clear that pragmatism must incline towards meliorism..." Pragmatism VIII https://www.gutenberg.org/files/5116/5116-h/5116-h.htm#link2H_4_0002
Re: Whitman. I think WJ exaggerates his indiscriminate "hurrah for the universe"etc. That poem about going to live with animals certainly implies a critique of better and worse ways of being human...
ReplyDelete“I could turn and live with animals, they are so placid and self-contained,
I stand and look at them long and long;
They do not sweat and whine about their condition.
They do not lie awake in the dark and weep for their sins.
Not one is dissatisfied, not one is demented with the mania of owning things,
Not one kneels to another, nor to his kind that lived thousands of years ago,
Not one is respectable or unhappy over the whole earth.”